Categories (Stoic)

Categories (Stoic)

The term Stoic Categories refers to Stoic ideas regarding Categories: the most fundamental classes of being for all things. The Stoics believed there were four categories (substance, quality, disposition, relative dispostion) which were the ultimate divisions. Since we do not now possess even a single complete work by Zeno of Citium, Cleanthes or Chrysippus what we do know must be pieced together from a number of sources: doxographies and the works of other philosophers who discuss the Stoics for their own purposes. [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/]

Overview

Our information comes from Plotinus and Simplicius, with additional evidence from Plutarch of Chaeronea and Sextus Empiricus. According to both Plotinus and Simplicius there were four Stoic categories, to wit:

* substance (ὑποκείμενον)
**The primary matter, formless substance, ("ousia") which makes up things.
* quality (ποιόν)
**The way in which matter is organized to form an individual object. In Stoic physics, a physical ingredient ("pneuma": air or breath) which informs the matter.
* somehow disposed (πως ἔχον)
**Particular characteristics, not present within the object, such as size, shape, action, and posture.
* somehow disposed in relation to something (πρός τί πως ἔχον)
**Characteristics which are related to other phenomenae, such as the position of an object within time and space relative to other objects.

A simple example of the Stoic categories in use is provided by Jacques Brunschwig:

I am a certain lump of matter, and thereby a substance, an existent something (and thus far that is all); I am a man, and this individual man that I am, and thereby qualified by a common quality and a peculiar one; I am sitting or standing, disposed in a certain way; I am the father of my children, the fellow citizen of my fellow citizens, disposed in a certain way in relation to something else. [Jacques Brunschwig, (2003), "The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics", ed. Brad Inwood, page 228, Cambridge University Press]

Background

Stoicism, like Aristotelianism is derived from Platonic and Socratic traditions. The Stoics held that all being (ὄντα) -- though not all things (τινά) -- are corporeal. They accepted the distinction between concrete bodies and abstract ones, but rejected Aristotle's teaching that purely incorporeal being exists. Thus, they accepted Anaxagoras' idea (as did Aristotle) that if an object is hot, it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object. But, unlike Aristotle, they extended the idea to cover all accidents. Thus if an object is red, it would be because some part of a universal red body had entered the object.

In addition, the Stoics differed from Aristotle in their sharp distinction between concrete and abstract terms. Technically speaking all four Stoic categories are of concrete bodies. For Aristotle "white, whiteness, heat," and "hot" were qualities. For the Stoics, however, quality refers to "white," but not "whiteness; hot," but not "heat." Furthermore, they believed that there are concrete bodies with no corresponding abstraction, something that makes no sense in Aristotelian terms.

It was apparent that the mere distinction between concrete substance and concrete quality was not a sufficient basis for logic. Socrates in the Hippias Major had pointed out problems in Anaxagoras' approach, explaining all attributes through their presence in a body in the way one body may be contained in another. In that dialog, Hippias tried to explain beauty to Socrates. Socrates finds fault with his explanations, that beauty is a beautiful maiden, that beauty is gold, that beauty is health, wealth and a long life.

Aristotle solved the problem in proposing that accidental attributes are non-substantial beings that inhere in substances. He defines this presence saying "By being 'present in a subject' I do not mean present as parts are present in a whole, but being incapable of existence apart from the said subject." ("The Categories" 1a 24-26)

Such incorporeal presence caused problems to the Stoics, who adhered to the Timaeus in saying that the οὐσία of a thing is its matter. It is easy to understand the problem. If there is an insubstantial being, "in Athens" somehow present in Socrates, causing him to be substantially present in Athens we seem to be faced with an infinite regression, for there would seem to be an insubstantial Socrates in the insubstantial Athens in Socrates, in Athens, etc. Ultimately, who is to say who is the real Socrates and what is the real Athens? Similar arguments can be made of Aristotle's other categories. Was there an insubstantial "running" in Archimedes causing him to run naked through the streets of Syracuse, shouting out his immortal "Eureka?" Was there an insubstantial fist in Athena causing her to strike Aphrodite as the Iliad recounts?

Once Hera spoke, Athena dashed off in pursuit,
delighted in her heart. Charging Aphrodite,
she struck her in the chest with her powerful fist. [http://www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/homer/iliad21.htm]
It was the effort to solve the problems raised by the Platonists and Peripatetics that led the Stoics to develop their categories, "somehow disposed" and "somehow disposed in relation to something." The fact that Stoicism, rather than either Platonism or Aristotelianism became the prominent philosophy of the ancient world is due in part to the approach they took to the problem.

According to Stephen Menn the first two categories, substance and quality, were recognized by Zeno. The fourth category "somehow disposed in relation to something" seems to have been developed by the time of Aristo. The third category, "somehow disposed" is first seen in Chrysippus.

The need for relative terms, seen in the fourth category "somehow disposed in relation to something" is more obvious than the need for the third category "somehow disposed" and so it seems to have arisen first.

Aristotle had used relative terms in a somewhat general way. "Those things are called relative, which, being either said to be of something else or related to something else, are explained by reference to that other thing." ("The Categories" 6a 37-38) Thus he says that "knowledge" and "the thing known" are relatives. One can certainly consider knowledge as something properly existing in its subject. Aristotle himself recognized a much different kind of relationship. "In respect of relation there is no proper change; for, without changing, a thing will be now greater and now less or equal, if that with which it is compared has changed in quantity." " [http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.14.xiv.html#95 (Metaphysics 1088a 33-35)] " In the first case, a relative term can be said to be something "in" its subject. In the second case, it can not. Thus, the need for "somehow disposed in relation to something" to explain how one thing can be relative to another without the presence of anything corporeal in a subject.

According to Stephen Menn, the third category, "somehow disposed" probably was recognized first in relation to the virtues. According to Socrates, virtue was a sort of knowledge. The wise man will act virtuously, since he will see it as the right thing to do. But the ignorant man can not avoid vice. The Stoic position held that a sage will possess all the virtues in their fullness. Aristo had argued that there is really only one virtue differentiated as "somehow disposed in relation to something." This seemed to be too much like the Megarian position. Chrysippus thus came to see the virtues as distinct bodies, inseparable from each other "somehow disposed" in themselves and not in relation to something. Thus the need for the third category.

Neoplatonic Critique

Plotinus criticized both Aristotle's Categories and those of the Stoics. His student Porphyry however defended Aristotle's scheme. He justified this by arguing that they be interpreted strictly as expressions, rather than as metaphysical realities. The approach can be justified, at least in part, by Aristotle's own words in "The Categories." Boëthius' acceptance of Porphyry's interpretation led to their being accepted by Scholastic philosophy.

The Stoic scheme did not fare as well. Plotinus wrote...

" Besides, if they make life and soul no more than this "pneuma,"what is the import of that repeated qualification of theirs "in acertain state," their refuge when they are compelled to recognize someacting principle apart from body? If not every pneuma is a soul, butthousands of them soulless, and only the pneuma in this "certainstate" is soul, what follows? Either this "certain state," thisshaping or configuration of things, is a real being or it is nothing. If it is nothing, only the pneuma exists, the "certain state"being no more than a word; this leads imperatively to the assertionthat Matter alone exists, Soul and God mere words, the lowest aloneis. If on the contrary this "configuration" is really existent-something distinct from the underlie or Matter, something residingin Matter but itself immaterial as not constructed out of Matter, thenit must be a Reason-Principle, incorporeal, a separate Nature. [http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/jod/texts/plotinus] "

Notes

Further reading

* Stephen Menn, "The Stoic Theory of Categories," in "Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Volume XVII: 1999," (Oxford, Oxford University Press) ISBN 0-19-825019-3, pp.215-47

External links

* " [http://www.formalontology.it/categories-stoics-plotinus.htm The Stoic Theory of Categories and Plotinus' Criticism] " with an extensive bibliography


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Categories (Aristotle) — Categories (Lat. Categoriae , Greek Κατηγορίαι Katēgoriai ) is a text from Aristotle s Organon that enumerates all the possible kinds of thing which can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition.The Categories places every object of human… …   Wikipedia

  • Diodotus the Stoic — Diodotus (Greek: Διόδοτος; fl. 1st century BC) was a Stoic philosopher, and was a friend of Cicero. He lived for most of his life in Rome in Cicero s house, where he instructed Cicero in Stoic philosophy and especially Logic.[1] Although Cicero… …   Wikipedia

  • Diotimus the Stoic — Diotimus (Greek: Διότιμος) was a Stoic philosopher, who lived c. 100 BC. He is said to have accused Epicurus of being depraved, and to have forged fifty letters, professing to have been written by Epicurus, to prove it.[1] According to Athenaeus …   Wikipedia

  • Chrysippus — This article is about the philosopher. For other people named Chrysippus, see Chrysippus (disambiguation). Chrysippus of Soli Roman copy of a Hellenistic bust of Chrysippus, British Museum Full name Chrysippus of Soli Born c. 279 BC …   Wikipedia

  • Seneca the Younger — Ancient bust of Seneca, part of a double herm (Antikensammlung Berlin) Lucius Annaeus Seneca (often known simply as Seneca) (ca. 4 BC – 65 AD) was a Roman Stoic philosopher, statesman, dramatist, and in one work humorist, of the Silver Age of… …   Wikipedia

  • Cleanthes — Full name Cleanthes Born c. 330 BC Assos Died c. 230 BC Athens Era Ancient philosophy Region Western Philosophy School …   Wikipedia

  • Lucius Annaeus Cornutus — Lucius Annaeus Cornutus, (Greek: Ἀνναῖος Κορνοῦτος), a Stoic philosopher, flourished in the reign of Nero (c. 60 AD), when his house in Rome was a school of philosophy. Contents 1 Life 2 Writings 2.1 Compendium of Greek Theology …   Wikipedia

  • Marcus Aurelius — Not to be confused with Aurelian. Marcus Aurelius 16th Emperor of the Roman Empire Bust of Marcus Aurelius in the Glyptothek, Munich …   Wikipedia

  • Stoicism — Stoicism, a school of Hellenistic philosophy, was founded in Athens by Zeno of Citium in the early third century BC. It concerns the active relationship between cosmic determinism and human freedom, and the belief that it is virtuous to maintain… …   Wikipedia

  • Diogenes of Babylon — For other uses, see Diogenes (disambiguation). Diogenes of Babylon (also known as Diogenes of Seleucia; c. 230 c. 150/140 BCE[1]) was a Stoic philosopher. He was the head of the Stoic school in Athens, and he was one …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”