Supposition theory

Supposition theory

Supposition theory was a branch of medieval logic that was probably aimed at giving accounts of issues similar to modern accounts of reference, plurality, tense, and modality, from within an Aristotelian context. Philosophers such as John Buridan, William of Ockham, William of Sherwood, Walter Burley, and Peter of Spain were key in developing it. By the 14th century it seems to have drifted into at least two fairly distinct theories, the theory of "supposition proper" which included a "ampliation" and is much like a theory of reference, and the theory of "modes of supposition" whose intended function is not clear.

upposition proper

Supposition was a semantic relation between a term and what it is being used to talk about.So, for example, in the suggestion "Drink another cup" the term "cup" is suppositing for the wine contained in the cup.The logical "suppositum" of a term was the object the term referred to, (in grammar "suppositum" was used in a different way). However, supposition was a different semantic relationship than signification. Signification was a conventional relationship between utterances and objects mediated by the particularities of a language. "Poculum" signifies in Latin, what "cup" signifies in English. Signification is the imposition of a meaning on an utterance, but supposition is taking a meaningful term as standing in for something. According to Peter of Spain "Hence signification is prior to supposition. Neither do they belong to the same thing. For to signify belongs to an utterance, but to supposit belongs to a term already, as it were, put together out of an utterance and a signification." An easy way to see the difference is in our "drink another cup" example. Here "cup" as an utterance signifies a cup as an object, but "cup" as a term of the language English is being used to supposit for the wine contained in the cup.

Medieval logicians divided supposition into many different kinds, and the jargons for the different kinds, and their relations and what they all mean get complex, and differ greatly from logician to logician. Paul Spade's webpage has a series of helpful diagrams here. The most important division is probably between material, simple, personal, and improper supposition. A term supposits materially, when it is used to stand in for an utterance or inscription, rather than for what is signifies. When I say "Cup is a monosyllabic word," I am using the word "cup" to supposit materially for the utterance "cup" rather than for a piece of pottery. Material supposition is a medieval way of doing the work we would do today by using quotation marks. According to Ockham ("Summa of Logic" I64, 8) "Simple supposition occurs when a term supposits for an intention of the soul, but is not take significatively." The idea is that simple signification happens when the term is standing in for a human concept rather than for the object itself. If I say "Cups are an important type of pottery" the term "cups" is not standing in for any particular cup, but for the idea of a cup in the human mind (according to Ockham, and many medieval logicians, but not according to John Buridan). Personal supposition in contrast is when the term supposits for what is signifies. If I say "Pass me the cup" the term "cup" is standing in for the object that is called a "cup" in English, so it is in personal supposition. A term is in improper supposition, if it is suppositing for an object, but a different object than it signifies, as in my example "Drink another cup."

Modes of supposition

Personal Supposition was further divided in types such as discrete, determinate, merely confused, and confused and distributive. In 1966 T.K. Scott proposed giving a separate name for Medieval discussions of the subvarieties of personal supposition, because he thought it was a fairly distinct issue from the other varieties of supposition. He proposed calling the subvarieties of personal supposition a theory of "modes of supposition."

The Medieval logicians give elaborate sets of syntactical rules for determining when a term supposits discretely, determinately, confusedly, or confusedly and distributively. So for example the subject of a negative claim, or indefinite one supposits determinately, but the subject of a singular claim supposits discretely, while the subject of an affirmative claim supposits confusedly and determinately. Albert of Saxony gives 15 rules for determining which type of personal supposition a term is using. Further the medieval logicians did not seem to dispute about the details of the syntactic rules for determining type of personal supposition. These rules seem to be important because they were linked to theories of descent to particulars and ascent from particulars.

When I say "I want to buy a cup" I've made an indefintate affirmative claim, with "cup" as the predicate term. Further cup is a common term, including many particular cups within it. So if I "descend to particulars" I can re-phrase my claim as "I want to buy this cup or I want to buy that cup, or I want to buy that other cup - and so on for all cups." If I had an infinite disjunction of all particular cups, it could stand in for the term cup, in its simple supposition in "I want to buy a cup." This is called determinate supposition. That is when I say "I want to buy a cup" I mean some determinate cup, but I don't necessarily know which one yet. Likewise if I say "Some cup isn't a table," I could substitute "This cup isn't a table, or that cup isn't a table or ..."

On the other hand if I say "No cup is a table", I don't mean "This cup isn't a table or that one isn't a table or ..." I mean "This cup isn't a table, AND that cup isn't a table, AND that other cup isn't a table, AND ...". Here I am referring not to a determinate particular cup, but to all cups "fused" together, that is all cups "confusedly." This is called confused and distributive supposition.

If I say "This cup is made of gold" I cannot descend to a disjunction of particulars, or to a conjunction of particulars, but only because "this cup" is already a particular. This kind of personal supposition is called discrete supposition.

However, the predicate of a universal affirmative claim won't really fit any of these models. "All coffee cups are cups" does not imply "All coffee cups are this cup, or all coffee cups are that cup, or ...", but still less does it imply "All coffee cups are this cup, and all coffee cups are that cup, and ...". On the other hand, if it happened to be the case that their was only one coffee cup left in the world, it would be true that "All coffee cup are that cup", so I can validly infer from "All coffee cups are that cup", to "All coffee cups are cups". Here descent to disjunction fails, and descent to conjunction fails, but "ascent from particulars" is valid. This is called "merely confused supposition."

That is basically how the theory works, a much thornier problem is exactly what the theory is for. Some commentors, like Michael Loux, have suggested that the theory of ascent and descent to particulars is intended to provide truth conditions for the quantifiers. T. K. Scott has suggested that the theory of supposition proper was designed to answer the question "What kind of thing are you talking about?" but the theory of personal supposition was aimed at answering the question "How many of them are you talking about?" Paul Spade has suggested that by the 14th century the theory of modes of personal supposition wasn't aimed at anything at all anymore.

Ampliation

When I say "No cups are made of lead", "cups" supposits for all the cups that exist. But if I say "Some cups were made of lead in Roman times" "cups" cannot just be suppositing for all the cups that exist, but for cups in the past as well. Here I am expanding the normal supposition of the terms I use. Peter of Spain says "Ampliation is the extension of a common term from a lesser supposition to a greater one." In practice, if I speak of the past, or the future, or make a modal claim, the terms I use get ampliated to supposit for past things, future things, or possible things, rather than their usual supposition for present actual things. Thus, ampliation becomes the medieval theory for explaining modal and tense logics within the theory of supposition.

ources

*Buridan, John. Sophisms on Meaning and Truth (New York: Appleton-Temple-Crofts 1966)
*Kneale, William & Martha Kneale. Development of Logic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962)
*Kretzmann, Norman, Anthony Kenny & Jan Pinborg. Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).
*Loux, Michael "Ockham on Generality" in Ockham's Theory of Terms (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974)
*Read, S. 'Medieval Theories: Properties of Terms at [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/medieval-terms]
*Scott, T.K. "Introduction" to Buridan, Sophisms on Meaning and Truth (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1966)
*Spade, Paul "Thoughts, Words, and Things: An Introduction to Late Medieval Logic and Semantic Theory" at http://pvspade.com/Logic/noframes/download.html
*Spain, Peter of "Tractatus, Called Afterwards Summule Logicales" (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1972)

External links

* [http://www.formalontology.it/supposition.htm Annotated bibliography on the medieval theories of supposition and mental language]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • supposition theory — noun Theory in medieval Europe to explain then modern events from an Aristotelian context …   Wiktionary

  • theory — I noun assumption, belief, conjecture, doctrina, doctrine, dogma, guesswork, hypothesis, ideology, opinion, philosophy, postulate, presupposition, proposition, ratio, speculation, supposition, surmise, thesis, thought, untested opinion, view… …   Law dictionary

  • supposition — I noun assumption, belief, conception, coniectura, conjecture, guess, hypothesis, likelihood, likeliness, opinio, opinion, position, postulate, premise, presumption, probability, speculation, supposal, surmise, suspicion, theorem, theory, thesis… …   Law dictionary

  • theory — ► NOUN (pl. theories) 1) a supposition or a system of ideas intended to explain something, especially one based on general principles independent of the thing to be explained. 2) an idea accounting for or justifying something. 3) a set of… …   English terms dictionary

  • supposition — [n] guess, belief apriorism, assumption, condition, conjecture, doubt, guessing, guesstimate*, guesswork, hunch, hypothesis, idea, likelihood, notion, opinion, posit, postulate, postulation, premise, presumption, presupposition, rough guess*,… …   New thesaurus

  • theory — [n] hypothesis, belief approach, argument, assumption, base, basis, code, codification, concept, conditions, conjecture, doctrine, dogma, feeling, formularization, foundation, grounds, guess, guesswork, hunch, idea, ideology, impression, method,… …   New thesaurus

  • supposition — I (New American Roget s College Thesaurus) Assumption Nouns 1. supposition, assumption, postulation, condition (see qualification); presupposition, hypothesis, postulate, theory, data; proposition, position; thesis, theorem; proposal; conceit;… …   English dictionary for students

  • Supposition — (Roget s Thesaurus) < N PARAG:Supposition >N GRP: N 1 Sgm: N 1 supposition supposition assumption assumed position postulation condition presupposition hypothesis postulate postulatum theory Sgm: N 1 thesis thesis th …   English dictionary for students

  • theory — I (New American Roget s College Thesaurus) n. speculation, surmise, conjecture; contemplation; principle, philosophy, doctrine; hypothesis; guess, idea, plan. See supposition. II (Roget s IV) n. 1. [Principles] Syn. law, principles, postulates,… …   English dictionary for students

  • theory — n. (pl. ies) 1 a supposition or system of ideas explaining something, esp. one based on general principles independent of the particular things to be explained (opp. HYPOTHESIS) (atomic theory; theory of evolution). 2 a speculative (esp.… …   Useful english dictionary

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”